Monday, March 10, 2014
In the Hawai`i GMO battles, everyone cites The Precautionary Principle: But which one?
The Precautionary Principle is used and often abused in
response to any number of major public issues.
The problem is that while it seems simple, there is no
consensus on how to apply it. The term has multiple meanings, and some of them
are in pretty direct conflict with each other.
As most folks understand it, the principle translates to
this: if there’s risk, use extra caution.
But that’s not an enforceable standard. Which side
determines whether there is risk? Who must show whether that risk is
significant? How much caution is required? And what if an action has benefits
that outweigh the risks—can you balance those factors?
Some people argue that if there is any possible risk, the action
must be prohibited. In the heated discussions over genetically modified crops,
even folks supporting a total ban on GMOs say that’s too harsh a standard.
British mathematician Peter T. Saunders, who has argued
before the U.S. Congress in support of a moratorium on all GMO research, says: “The
principle does not, as some critics claim, require industry to provide absolute
proof that something new is safe. That would be an impossible demand and would
indeed stop technology dead in its tracks.”
That said, the libertarian Cato Institute argues that even
weaker versions of The Precautionary Principle establish an impossible
standard. In a 2002 paper, Cato calls it The Paralyzing Principle.
And it is not even always protective of health and the
environment. The Precautionary Principle has occasionally been used AGAINST the
environment, preventing actions that promote conservation on the grounds that
they may have negative conseuences as well.
Commentators have identified three versions of the
principle: weak, moderate and strong.
The “weak” version requires actual evidence of environmental
harm rather than a suspicion of it. It can place the burden of proof of harm on
those proposing regulation of an activity. And it may permit a balancing of the cost of
mitigation against the benefits of the activity.
In the Hawaiian GMO controversy, as an example, the anti-GM
forces would be required to prove that there are more than anecdotal impacts of
GM farming. And regulations on those growing genetically modified crops could
be balanced against the economic and other costs of shutting down those
businesses.
A “moderate version,” as in the United Kingdom Biodiversity
Action Plan, suggests actual evidence isn’t needed, but “a significant chance
of damage” is. The burden of proof is still with those insisting on precaution.
And if that case is made, balancing of costs and benefits may not be required.
A “strong” version of The Precautionary Principle put the
burden on the person or agency proposing an activity to prove it will not cause
significant harm. In this example, Hawai`i’s seed industry would need to
provide evidence that their activities are benign.
With so much variation, one issue with asserting The
Precautionary Principle, is: “Which Precautionary Principle?”
One of the early attempts to define The Precautionary
Principle in legal terms came in the 1982 United Nations Charter for Nature. It
said, “When an activity raises threats of harm to human health or the
environment, precautionary measures should be taken even if some cause and effect
relationships are not established scientifically. In this context the proponent
of the activity, rather than the public, should bear the burden of proof.”
The 1992 Rio Declaration, which was also adopted by the 2000
Cartagena Protocol on Biosafety says in Principle 15: “Where there are threats
of serious or irreversible damage, lack of full scientific certainty shall not
be used as a reason for postponing cost-effective measures to prevent environmental
degradation.”
The Science and Environmental Health Network puts that alittle more clearly: “When the health of humans and the environment is at
stake, it may not be necessary to wait for scientific certainty to take
protective action.”
That is a restatement of the Wingspread Statement on the
Precautionary Principle: “When an activity raises threats of harm to human
health or the environment, precautionary measures should be taken even if some
cause and effect relationships are not fully established scientifically.”
Supporters of a stronger version argue that it protects
human health, protects the environment and ultimately makes the planet a safer
place. Opponents argue that it stifles innovation, raises costs, provides
regulators with too much power since no version is an entirely clear standard, and
that it promotes legal challenge.
© Jan TenBruggencate 2014
Posted by Jan T at 1:43 PM
Labels: Agriculture, Conservation, Government, Health/Medical, Sustainability, technology
Subscribe to:
Post Comments (Atom)
No comments:
Post a Comment